Conclusion
Having
outlined the notion of personality traits here, it seems that many
new questions are raised. One of the first ones that may appear is
why I've gone to the trouble of highlighting Eyesenck's flawed
personality trait studies.
Surely I could be accused of constructing
a strawman argument from 1960s research and launching an attack
against that? Furthermore, you may be wondering why I have written
such a lengthy mini series and how this is relevant. Well, I will
spell out why I went to the trouble of doing this semi-academic
piece, and highlight what it might achieve.
It is of
little surprise that Eyesenck's ideas have caught on. The basic
ideas behind his argument have formed the basis for much on going
research. It is only within the last 10 years that the voices of
critics like Mischel have been heeded in the mainstream.
Meanwhile, the mainstream has had to try and fight off the eliminative
materialist claims that we should be abandoning the folk theory and
trying to form a proper theory of mind over the past 30 years.
It
seems we are at the stage where we have to pay attention to the way
in which we have carved up the psychological domain. This means
we're going to have to re-evaluate the categorisations that we have
traditionally imposed.
The endurance of Eyesenck's theory bears
testament to the fact that he appeals to common sense and appeals to
the way in which we have been carving up the psychological domain.
The main
problem with trait theory centres around the assumption that traits
actually exist. There are newer, and presumably better, personality
theories around these days but they all make
the assumption that we fit in to categories or types.
As I have
stated in this discussion, we do conform to predictable patterns of
behaviour at times and we certainly do not need to deny this. Nor do
we need to deny that categories have practical use. We have also
admitted that we have a cultural assumption that traits exist built
right in to our language.
It is the tendency of the human mind to
divide the world in to categories and using traits is one way in
which people in our social worlds become intelligible.
Implicit
in this view is that these traits are independent from our agency.
That is, we have no control over our tendency to get angry, be
pessimistic etc. In this sense we are referring to some kind of
mechanism that we have no control over. Interestingly enough, we
identify strongly with our personality traits and we believe them to
make some kind of statement about who we really are.
We might be
tempted to identify other aspects of our body which we have no
control over, like being ginger or being optimistic. We may identify
with things that we consciously choose, like being a raver or
whatever it is the kids call themselves these days (Yes, I'm not down
with the kids anymore!). However, it is usually just the case that we
utilise circular logic to form a web of deceit, which masquerades as
our identity, that prevents us from entertaining the truth about the
illusory self.
The
notion of self hood is reliant in part on the multiple “I am 'a', I
am also 'b', and 'c'” modes of identification. E.g. I am ginger, I
am optimistic, I am a raver. It is likely that during your
phenomenological investigation in to the self you will try to say
that the self is identical to x, y, or z.
E.g. The self is the brain,
the self is the body, The self is memory and so on.
Nobody
ever takes the time to look behind what these concepts refer to in
real life, as these modes are representative of the constraints in
which we think.
This
is why it is not a logical endeavour to realise Anatta.
The
trick to getting this Anatta insight is in part exposing the
emptiness of those a, b, c labels, and then refuting the assumptions
that the self is x, y, or z.
Once these notions have been smashed to
pieces, then it is a simple case of honest looking. I am going to
post the above paragraph in numerous places because it is a succinct
outline of the basic process you need to use.
I used to harp on about
looking, but it is also necessary to smash apart the web of deceit by
utilising a bit of logic first. When you see these assumptions no
longer work logically you can discard them and systematically
demolish the foundations upon which the illusory self is based.
We
all start out from a position where we are bounded by the belief that
we are an enduring self that has such and such 'properties'. We have
a tendency to objectify ourselves as having the 'properties' of
traits, much like we can treat other people as objects of experience.
I wanted to draw this parallel here, not because we normally treat
friends and family like objects, but because we think in terms of all
'things' as having enduring properties.
What
we mean here is the way we describe subjects and objects in dualistic
terms, results in us assigning attributes to people which are of
course consistent with our categorisation of traits.
These
traits are predicated as aspects of the self, much like properties
are the predicates of objects in our language.
So
take the 'outgoing' trait as an example. Imagine that you are
outgoing and sociable and by some awful freak event, you lose the use
of your vocal cords and become dumb. What would happen to this
personality trait then? You might claim 'I'm outgoing and sociable'
previously.
However, what would we make of this claim if you were
struck down with this awful tragedy?
Nothing
would have changed about your so called traits, however, this
outgoing trait is contingent on your being able to talk. In this
sense, the predicate would become unintelligible to somebody who just
met you, and did not know you prior to your unfortunate change in
circumstance.
Clearly, these constructs are quite empty when we
consider such extremes.
When
we are talking about contingencies of circumstance these are rather
fleeting things which can easily change, instead of being the solid
and enduring things we think they are. We
can start to look at our own personality traits and look at the ways
in which we think they define us.
The point of this whole piece
really, is to smash apart the solidity of personality traits and
highlight the shaky grounds on which they are based.
It is not so
much that we needed to disprove traits exist (although I have cast
serious doubt on the claim), it is just to show that the solid
assumptions we use to prop up our notions of selfhood are really
quite flimsy when we examine them with a degree of scrutiny.
Once
we start to hack away at the logic behind personality traits, it
seems more and more likely that we are really dealing with an
arbitrary notion of category construction, that is purely linguistic.
It
should be noted at this point, that different cultures have different
categories of behaviour. As such, cross-cultural trait models have a
cut down five trait model, to try and apply it universally across the
board. In this sense it is only our arrogance that leads us to assume
that there are a definitive of set of objective trait correlates,
that conform to the English language.
The
reality seems to suggest that traits are merely the construction of
personal values using shared language. In more scientific terms,
traits theory is an attempt to treat people as having objective
aspects, that can be medically categorised and diagnosed.
This
of course has its roots in the orthodoxy of physicalism, which is
now an untenable position in philosophy of mind and has since been
superseded with functionalism. I argued earlier that we cannot
delineate between traits and our personal construction of meaning
convincingly.
For this reason, I am convinced that a revised
functionalist account of trait theory could not work, but
functionalism certainly may be able to account for behaviour by
identifying patterning in neural networks. However, this would
constitute an as yet unspecified theory, and would abandon the
constraints of traditional notions of traits.
This new theory would
be something that perhaps many eliminative materialists would
endorse.
The
evidence for the personal construction theory of traits seems to fit
our observations. The lack of evidence for traditional notions of
traits is compounded by the problems we have when we point to
conventions of language.
Could
it really be the case that nobody has objective personality traits,
and the myth of the enduring personality is a fiction? For me, the
fact that our ideas about personality are completely empty could be
somewhat disconcerting and radical on the one hand.
It seems that
when I think about the ones I love and that they have no personality,
other than what I construct in my own mind is counter intuitive.
However, once we factor in the multiplicity of events and the
vicissitudes of our different behaviours, it becomes clear that these
categorisations of traits are too rigid for the rich and wonderful
varieties of behaviour that our fellow human beings are capable of.
When
viewed in this sense, it seems that quite the opposite is the case
and traits are counter-intuitive.
The
notion of trying to apply a narrow series of categories that apply to
traits, would be far too restrictive to account for the dynamic
nature of the unfolding of our lives. If we were only capable of
behaving along a dimensional axis for each trait, then we would be
somewhat robotic and more predictable in our responses to life's
events.
The fact of the matter is that we are far more unpredictable
and are capable of surprising acts, and confounding expectations. We
try to impose order on the world by using traits but this does not
entail that the way we do so, or the way we learned culturally to do
so, is definitive in any way.
If
we take the view of Heidegger, the subject/ object dichotomy is
merely one way of being, and is a useful way to look at the world.
However, restricting ourselves to this view means that we miss out on
the modes of being where we don't view people as having properties.
Such times would be when we are in the throes of sporting
competition, having a laugh with friends in the pub, or losing
yourself in a lovers kiss.
The
point here, is simply that we need to differentiate between the way
we think about people objectively when we reflect on them, and the
way we experience them in the flow of life. It makes sense that we
try to make predictions about how others might behave, or rationalise
and criticise peoples actions.
When doing this though, we are always
doing it in a temporal sense outside of the present moment. When
using traits we are talking about past and future actions.
I
will leave it for you to decide where trait theory fits in to the
present moment, but rest assured you will find it difficult to find
relevance in the present moment, other than within a temporal
narrative about time. That is, every time we think about traits it is
in a temporal sense and does not conform to our 'being in the world'
direct experience of socialising.
We could of course be talking about
drama when socialising in the present moment, and we could be
focussed on why someone acted in such and such a manner. Again
though, we would be referring to our temporal ideas and our
experience of traits in the present moment would be limited to the
act of talking itself, and the mental phenomena that arises during
our chain of reasoning.
It
seems then, that the notion of an enduring personality is nothing
more than a myth in the grand scheme of things. Particularly where we
use the categorisations available in our linguistic community.
It
was an unfounded assumption that these categorisations actually
related to physical states and whilst it appears logical to divide
the domain of traits in this way, we've seen that this is actually
empty.
It seems that personality is a mysterious phenomenon that we
think we can know, but we cannot easily, or coherently, conceptualise
it in the way we thought we could.
References:
Butt,
T. (2012) 'Critical
Readings in Social Psychology',
Ch. 3, 2nd
edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
Butt,
T. (2004) 'Understanding
People',
ch.1, Basingstoke & New York, Palgrave Macmillan.
Eysenck,
H.J & Rachman, S. (2012 [1965]) 'Dimensions
of Personality',
in Butt, T (2012) 'Critical
Readings in Social Psychology',
ch.3, 2nd
edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
Fisher,
H (2013) Extract of essay taken from 'On
Temperament' in
Brockman,
J (2013 [2012]) This
will make you smarter.
Last
Accessed 23/11/14
Holloway,
W. (2012) 'Social
Psychology Matters',
ch.3, 2nd
edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
Richards,
G. (2002) 'Putting
Psychology
in its Place:A
Critical Historical Overview',
ch. 18, 2nd
edition, Sussex, Psychology Press.