- Butt, T. (2012) 'Critical Readings in Social Psychology', Ch. 3, 2nd edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
- Butt, T. (2004) 'Understanding People', ch.1, Basingstoke & New York, Palgrave Macmillan.
- Eysenck, H.J & Rachman, S. (2012 [1965]) 'Dimensions of Personality', in Butt, T (2012) 'Critical Readings in Social Psychology', ch.3, 2nd edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
- Fisher, H (2013) Extract of essay taken from 'On Temperament' in Brockman, J (2013 [2012]) This will make you smarter.Last Accessed 23/11/14
- Holloway, W. (2012) 'Social Psychology Matters', ch.3, 2nd edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
- Richards, G. (2002) 'Putting Psychology in its Place:A Critical Historical Overview', ch. 18, 2nd edition, Sussex, Psychology Press.
Showing posts with label dispositions. Show all posts
Showing posts with label dispositions. Show all posts
Sunday, 23 November 2014
Conclusion
Having
outlined the notion of personality traits here, it seems that many
new questions are raised. One of the first ones that may appear is
why I've gone to the trouble of highlighting Eyesenck's flawed
personality trait studies.
Surely I could be accused of constructing
a strawman argument from 1960s research and launching an attack
against that? Furthermore, you may be wondering why I have written
such a lengthy mini series and how this is relevant. Well, I will
spell out why I went to the trouble of doing this semi-academic
piece, and highlight what it might achieve.
It is of
little surprise that Eyesenck's ideas have caught on. The basic
ideas behind his argument have formed the basis for much on going
research. It is only within the last 10 years that the voices of
critics like Mischel have been heeded in the mainstream.
Meanwhile, the mainstream has had to try and fight off the eliminative
materialist claims that we should be abandoning the folk theory and
trying to form a proper theory of mind over the past 30 years.
It
seems we are at the stage where we have to pay attention to the way
in which we have carved up the psychological domain. This means
we're going to have to re-evaluate the categorisations that we have
traditionally imposed.
The endurance of Eyesenck's theory bears
testament to the fact that he appeals to common sense and appeals to
the way in which we have been carving up the psychological domain.
The main
problem with trait theory centres around the assumption that traits
actually exist. There are newer, and presumably better, personality
theories around these days but they all make
the assumption that we fit in to categories or types.
As I have
stated in this discussion, we do conform to predictable patterns of
behaviour at times and we certainly do not need to deny this. Nor do
we need to deny that categories have practical use. We have also
admitted that we have a cultural assumption that traits exist built
right in to our language.
It is the tendency of the human mind to
divide the world in to categories and using traits is one way in
which people in our social worlds become intelligible.
Implicit
in this view is that these traits are independent from our agency.
That is, we have no control over our tendency to get angry, be
pessimistic etc. In this sense we are referring to some kind of
mechanism that we have no control over. Interestingly enough, we
identify strongly with our personality traits and we believe them to
make some kind of statement about who we really are.
We might be
tempted to identify other aspects of our body which we have no
control over, like being ginger or being optimistic. We may identify
with things that we consciously choose, like being a raver or
whatever it is the kids call themselves these days (Yes, I'm not down
with the kids anymore!). However, it is usually just the case that we
utilise circular logic to form a web of deceit, which masquerades as
our identity, that prevents us from entertaining the truth about the
illusory self.
The
notion of self hood is reliant in part on the multiple “I am 'a', I
am also 'b', and 'c'” modes of identification. E.g. I am ginger, I
am optimistic, I am a raver. It is likely that during your
phenomenological investigation in to the self you will try to say
that the self is identical to x, y, or z.
E.g. The self is the brain,
the self is the body, The self is memory and so on.
Nobody
ever takes the time to look behind what these concepts refer to in
real life, as these modes are representative of the constraints in
which we think.
This
is why it is not a logical endeavour to realise Anatta.
The
trick to getting this Anatta insight is in part exposing the
emptiness of those a, b, c labels, and then refuting the assumptions
that the self is x, y, or z.
Once these notions have been smashed to
pieces, then it is a simple case of honest looking. I am going to
post the above paragraph in numerous places because it is a succinct
outline of the basic process you need to use.
I used to harp on about
looking, but it is also necessary to smash apart the web of deceit by
utilising a bit of logic first. When you see these assumptions no
longer work logically you can discard them and systematically
demolish the foundations upon which the illusory self is based.
We
all start out from a position where we are bounded by the belief that
we are an enduring self that has such and such 'properties'. We have
a tendency to objectify ourselves as having the 'properties' of
traits, much like we can treat other people as objects of experience.
I wanted to draw this parallel here, not because we normally treat
friends and family like objects, but because we think in terms of all
'things' as having enduring properties.
What
we mean here is the way we describe subjects and objects in dualistic
terms, results in us assigning attributes to people which are of
course consistent with our categorisation of traits.
These
traits are predicated as aspects of the self, much like properties
are the predicates of objects in our language.
So
take the 'outgoing' trait as an example. Imagine that you are
outgoing and sociable and by some awful freak event, you lose the use
of your vocal cords and become dumb. What would happen to this
personality trait then? You might claim 'I'm outgoing and sociable'
previously.
However, what would we make of this claim if you were
struck down with this awful tragedy?
Nothing
would have changed about your so called traits, however, this
outgoing trait is contingent on your being able to talk. In this
sense, the predicate would become unintelligible to somebody who just
met you, and did not know you prior to your unfortunate change in
circumstance.
Clearly, these constructs are quite empty when we
consider such extremes.
When
we are talking about contingencies of circumstance these are rather
fleeting things which can easily change, instead of being the solid
and enduring things we think they are. We
can start to look at our own personality traits and look at the ways
in which we think they define us.
The point of this whole piece
really, is to smash apart the solidity of personality traits and
highlight the shaky grounds on which they are based.
It is not so
much that we needed to disprove traits exist (although I have cast
serious doubt on the claim), it is just to show that the solid
assumptions we use to prop up our notions of selfhood are really
quite flimsy when we examine them with a degree of scrutiny.
Once
we start to hack away at the logic behind personality traits, it
seems more and more likely that we are really dealing with an
arbitrary notion of category construction, that is purely linguistic.
It
should be noted at this point, that different cultures have different
categories of behaviour. As such, cross-cultural trait models have a
cut down five trait model, to try and apply it universally across the
board. In this sense it is only our arrogance that leads us to assume
that there are a definitive of set of objective trait correlates,
that conform to the English language.
The
reality seems to suggest that traits are merely the construction of
personal values using shared language. In more scientific terms,
traits theory is an attempt to treat people as having objective
aspects, that can be medically categorised and diagnosed.
This
of course has its roots in the orthodoxy of physicalism, which is
now an untenable position in philosophy of mind and has since been
superseded with functionalism. I argued earlier that we cannot
delineate between traits and our personal construction of meaning
convincingly.
For this reason, I am convinced that a revised
functionalist account of trait theory could not work, but
functionalism certainly may be able to account for behaviour by
identifying patterning in neural networks. However, this would
constitute an as yet unspecified theory, and would abandon the
constraints of traditional notions of traits.
This new theory would
be something that perhaps many eliminative materialists would
endorse.
The
evidence for the personal construction theory of traits seems to fit
our observations. The lack of evidence for traditional notions of
traits is compounded by the problems we have when we point to
conventions of language.
Could
it really be the case that nobody has objective personality traits,
and the myth of the enduring personality is a fiction? For me, the
fact that our ideas about personality are completely empty could be
somewhat disconcerting and radical on the one hand.
It seems that
when I think about the ones I love and that they have no personality,
other than what I construct in my own mind is counter intuitive.
However, once we factor in the multiplicity of events and the
vicissitudes of our different behaviours, it becomes clear that these
categorisations of traits are too rigid for the rich and wonderful
varieties of behaviour that our fellow human beings are capable of.
When
viewed in this sense, it seems that quite the opposite is the case
and traits are counter-intuitive.
The
notion of trying to apply a narrow series of categories that apply to
traits, would be far too restrictive to account for the dynamic
nature of the unfolding of our lives. If we were only capable of
behaving along a dimensional axis for each trait, then we would be
somewhat robotic and more predictable in our responses to life's
events.
The fact of the matter is that we are far more unpredictable
and are capable of surprising acts, and confounding expectations. We
try to impose order on the world by using traits but this does not
entail that the way we do so, or the way we learned culturally to do
so, is definitive in any way.
If
we take the view of Heidegger, the subject/ object dichotomy is
merely one way of being, and is a useful way to look at the world.
However, restricting ourselves to this view means that we miss out on
the modes of being where we don't view people as having properties.
Such times would be when we are in the throes of sporting
competition, having a laugh with friends in the pub, or losing
yourself in a lovers kiss.
The
point here, is simply that we need to differentiate between the way
we think about people objectively when we reflect on them, and the
way we experience them in the flow of life. It makes sense that we
try to make predictions about how others might behave, or rationalise
and criticise peoples actions.
When doing this though, we are always
doing it in a temporal sense outside of the present moment. When
using traits we are talking about past and future actions.
I
will leave it for you to decide where trait theory fits in to the
present moment, but rest assured you will find it difficult to find
relevance in the present moment, other than within a temporal
narrative about time. That is, every time we think about traits it is
in a temporal sense and does not conform to our 'being in the world'
direct experience of socialising.
We could of course be talking about
drama when socialising in the present moment, and we could be
focussed on why someone acted in such and such a manner. Again
though, we would be referring to our temporal ideas and our
experience of traits in the present moment would be limited to the
act of talking itself, and the mental phenomena that arises during
our chain of reasoning.
It
seems then, that the notion of an enduring personality is nothing
more than a myth in the grand scheme of things. Particularly where we
use the categorisations available in our linguistic community.
It
was an unfounded assumption that these categorisations actually
related to physical states and whilst it appears logical to divide
the domain of traits in this way, we've seen that this is actually
empty.
It seems that personality is a mysterious phenomenon that we
think we can know, but we cannot easily, or coherently, conceptualise
it in the way we thought we could.
References:
Monday, 17 November 2014
F.A.E - The Fundamental Attribution Error
In
rating people we have a propensity to commit the 'fundamental
attribution error'
which is where we
overvalue
the effect of human agency, and underestimate the effect of the
present situation in explaining behaviour (Butt, 2004).
To illustrate, when we have to slam on the breaks because of
someone's driving, we may well blame the poor skill and idiotic
driving of another.
However, we might be overlooking the fact that
they are lost and are unsure of where they are going, and had a
moment of panic. In this sense, we are biased towards prioritising
human agency, and underestimate the degree to which a situation
determines behaviour.
If
we apply this to Eysenck, he assumed widespread use of words by the general population pointed to the underlying objectivity of traits. Whilst we
need not deny there are stable patterns in peoples behaviour,
Eysenck's research was situated within this folk psychology paradigm
and any results he derived were simply reinforcing his theories about
the existence of traits, without an attempt to test the validity of
them.
In this sense, his entire research project begged the question,
since he simply assumed that our categorisations pointed to real
enduring qualities. In any case, any results he derived were simply a
collection of people committing the fundamental attribution error,
and this undermines his claim to objective validity.
The fundamental attribution error demonstrates our propensity to conform to the general populations assumptions about traits in everyday discourse, and assume these shape our agency. However, what we find is that Eyesenck simply reinforced these assumptions, by getting people to take part in his research program and not, even undertaking an independent verification of the existence of such traits. Moreover, his statistical measurement technology was flawed and we see that the case for objectivity here is very flimsy.
![]() |
Check out Dustinland's wicked cartoons: http://dustinland.com/archives/archives626.html |
This problem arises because Eyesenck simply drew a pattern from
statistical inference of observations as justification for his
theory. As Richards (2002) points out, the very psychometric survey
measurements that we undertake can cause reification; where we
falsely grant objective reality to the thing being measured.
To
give an example, we could design a religious survey in 1700 say, that
tried to measure devoutness to Christianity. We could make statements
such as "Homosexuality is a sin and punishable by death",
or "Witchcraft is rife in this village".
We could collate a
number of psychometric surveys and provide statistically derived
empirical results. However, from these results all we have achieved
is measuring a bunch of worthless religious assumptions.
We have not
proved that these assumptions are true, we have merely taken for
granted their truth and produced a load of mathematical workings out
to support our folly.
Furthermore, these questions may have seemed
valid in 1700 but were we to try and ask them now, they would sound
quite ridiculous to any Christian. In this case, if we have
supposedly measured devoutness to religion and the statements are
irrelevant now, we can ask what exactly would we have measured back
then?
The simple answer is that we have reified the concept
devoutness to religion and
would have been engaged in sophistry.
What
this tells us is that any psychometric studies are based on
assumptions, and they produce a load of clever sounding mathematics
that purport to back up these assumptions. All this is done without
ever actually backing up these assumptions with evidence.
What we
really find is that this methodology is utterly worthless as a
measure of truth, and in fact, this has been utilised as a tool by
those of lowly scruples, to engage in the most wretched acts of deceit.
It
should be of little surprise that this is the tool of choice for
charlatans in marketing, studies of 'public opinion', and your impotent government.
This
dangerous tool has been used to subvert the need to make claims based
on evidence, and you should be suspicious of any statistical
manipulations that are thrown at you.
However, we can
forgive Eyesenck as these facts were not known at the time, and he
genuinely believed he was advancing science. It should be clear to
you now though, that this questionnaire style methodology is fundamentally flawed and is
still abused to this day by those who engage in the art of
statistical manipulation.
Mischel's Criticisms
To
cast further doubt on Eyesenck's research, Mischel (1968) started to
assess the evidence for trait theories and found the key assumption
that Eysenck had made was incorrect. It should be starting to become
clear that Eyesenck had simply assumed stable personalities were
based on a structural arrangement of traits.
What Mischel discovered
was that this assumption is not justified. Mischel cited extensive
evidence that suggested the attributing of traits reflected the
prejudice of the person doing the attributing, who had to draw on a
culturally shared trait theory to frame their observations. Given
that we use trait theory in everyday parlance, any observation is
necessarily going to be couched in terms of traits. However, this
does not necessarily mean our cultural categorisations are pointing
to anything concrete.
Mischel
cited a study that used Eyesenck's methodology of rating people from
behind a screen, and using a psychometric survey to measure the
responses. However, this time they observed strangers briefly in one
condition, and in another observed people whom they knew personally.
This study yielded a striking finding that went right to the heart of
this kind of objective methodology. It was found that those doing the
rating,
produced the same stable trait structure in strangers that they
observed very briefly, as in those that they knew well
(Butt, 2012).
This showed that under controlled conditions, subjects
were prejudicial in their attribution of personality
traits to strangers, and were willing to attribute them on very
little evidence. It also showed that these attributions were based on
the way they personally attributed traits to those they knew well
(Butt, 2004).
This
clearly demonstrated the error on which personality research was
based. It
is only natural, given the knowledge was situated in a paradigm that
accepted folk psychological doctrine, that through seeing statistical
patterns, practitioners could devise psychological categories for
people in order to determine treatments.
This kind of categorisation
is now widely acknowledged to be unreliable and PCT actually denies
this is useful, since it aims to understand the individual and
acknowledges there are many individual differences, rather than
narrow categorical dimensions.
Interestingly,
PCT would embrace this subjective aspect of a person doing the
personality construction, because when listening to how they
construct someone's personality we can uncover some of the meanings
this process has for them, and how they perceive the world.
To this
extent as a phenomenological exercise we can discover how people form
their constructions, and perhaps some of the assumptions participants make. However, this endeavour fits in to the field of social psychology, and we would be moving beyond the scope of this essay.
Conclusion here
Conclusion here
Thursday, 16 October 2014
Having
outlined the idea of trait theory and why it does not seem to work,
we will look to Personal
Construct Theory (PCT), which
suggests that we construct peoples personalities. To explain
this we might look towards one of the common paradoxes that arises in
assigning traits.
For
example, Fred may perceive upon meeting Gerald that he is loud and
obnoxious. However, Harry may may meet Gerald and perceive him as
outgoing and fun. In this sense, we look to the way Fred and Harry
attribute these traits and construct Gerald's personality. In
this sense we are looking towards our personal construction of
meaning.
In
theorising about personalities, we need to consider the extent to
which we construct our own versions of individual differences. This
PCT suggests that personality attribution is based on our own
theories about ourselves and others, which are directly influenced by
our preferences and meanings.
In
this sense, PCT is a form of phenomenological description extracted
from individuals and makes it a qualitative methodology that steps
out of the experimental paradigm, and focuses on understanding
individuals rather than categorising them (Butt, 2012).
In
our above example it is plain to see that Gerald is constructed
differently by Fred and Harry, so which, if either of them, is
correct? If we are talking about objectively true traits, then a
trait theorist would maintain one of them has to be wrong. It may be
that Harry is correctly being objective and Fred has taken a
disliking to Gerald.
How
could we be sure who was correct though?
How
each person makes sense of the world, influences how they perceive
things. The only way to be sure would be to go through an objective
assessment in a psychology lab. We will show this is problematic as
our next task, but an alternative to trait theory might be to listen
to Fred and Harry's construction of meaning through their own
phenomenological accounts.
We would discover the meanings they bring to bear on the
world and in this sense, PCT would seek to understand rather than try
to carve up the domain in to categories. PCT would take account of
the fact that we all have different likes and dislikes, which a trait
theory would fail to capture.
This leaves trait theory stuck trying to capture the objective
qualities of a person, independent of our experience of them.
Implicit in the assumption of trait theory is that people have
objective and measurable qualities, that are distinct and enduring.
The
reality shows us that we actually bring our own presuppositions and
preferences to the table when deciding what opinion we make of
people. Trait theory does not take account of this fact, and tries to
claim that people have objective qualities regardless of our view of
them.
However,
what we see is that this so called objective view cannot be separated
from our opinion. For example, even if we are told Gerald is fun and
outgoing, we may simply dislike him. It is not irrational to dislike
somebody, even if we find no good logical reason. We may be
questioned about why we dislike someone, but it is somewhat absurd to
claim that really he is an objectively outgoing person, when we find
him annoying and rude.
This
is because we may never experience this 'fact'. We might assent that
we have made an error of judgement, however, this can have no bearing
upon the validity of our intuition towards people, or influence our
viewpoint.
Here we are looking towards the fact that trait theory is
faced with the absurdity of trying to say that the multiple ways of
constructing people are incorrect, and there is one true objective
account of an individual. However, in real life people do not show up
in such a manner and this should point us to the error in this chain
of reasoning.
Having
outlined the basics of PCT,
we can start to make use of the criticisms its
advocates have made towards Trait theory, and show how a trait
theorists objective analysis and laboratory work is fraught with
problems.
Firstly,
the very foundations of Eysenck's research is challenged, since it
made use of statistical analyses to derive his personality index.
Remember, he used a factor analysis in order to group descriptions
together to form his list of 32 traits. To achieve this, he used a
psychometric questionnaire of the type where a mark is placed on a
numbered scale.
Such
surveys are characterised by 'strongly agree' or 'strongly disagree'
being placed at either end of this scale, and the respondent simply
circles a number to state the degree to which they agree or disagree
with a statement.
The
methodology of Eyesenck's work was to have subjects with these style questionnaires sat behind a one way window, where they observed
people in a room.
The idea was that the observers rated the
personality of those being observed. After a significant number of
repetitions with different observers, Eyesenck collected the results
together and conducted his factor analysis. In this sense he had the
significance of mathematics and empirically valid results to work
from.
However, it is at this stage where multiple problems emerge.
Sunday, 5 October 2014
At
this point, a trait theory might like to invoke the concept of
neurotransmitters. Implicit in trait theory is the need to point to
neurotransmitters as being the cause of behaviour. It may seem so far that I have ignored the idea of
neurotransmitters being influential in this process, and am dismissing
their importance.
It may be the case that since physical and mental
states are one and the same thing, John's new way of thinking after
CBT is a result of a change in the balance of neurotransmitters.
We
could argue about the plasticity of the brain and how it adapts over
time, and this relates to the experiential component we described
previously. Going back to John's condition, a trait theorist could
bite the bullet and suggest that being shy is an experiential
disposition, or 'trait of character' as Fisher writes.
John
was only affected by anxiety in the presence of strangers, and a
trait theorist could claim that this is a purely experiential
component. If we were able to establish a link between
neurotransmitters and behaviour this would support this line of
argumentation.
Implicit
to such a counter-argument is that we will act the same way in
similar situations because we have enduring traits. To account for
any deviation from this we have to appeal to dimensionality and allow
that neurotransmitters influence our behaviour along a dimensional
axis.
However, this leaves little room for manoeuvre when we consider
that we may have major life events that cause our behaviour to change
drastically from the traits we are ascribed. A death or traumatic
event in the family may cause our behaviour to deviate from these
fluctuations in dimensionality.
This might mean we are enveloped in a
terrible sense of melancholy that is somewhat out of character and is
of a temporal duration. It is pushing the bounds of trait theory too
far if we were to suggest that new traits appear, or we swing to
extremes on fixed dimensional planes.
This account would be missing
out on the kind of volatile mood swings, memories, and projections
that would feedback into our psychological world during a traumatic
time. A functionalist account might be better placed to capture this
aspect because it would not rely solely on neurotransmitters*. It
allows causal interactions between our mental and physical states,
however, trait theory is not afforded this luxury, since its aim is
to explain psychological differences in purely physical terms.
*
Footnote: A more advanced trait theory might like to try and exploit
this functionalist view, however, this would be untenable for reasons
we will outline shortly. Essentially, this boils down to the fact
that we cannot clearly delineate between traits and our own personal
view point. We will treat this matter fully in due course.
Perhaps
more damaging to trait theory is the whole edifice of this argument
stands or falls on the assumption that neurotransmitters are the
cause of our behaviours. Butt pointed out that neurotransmitters may
be sufficient but not necessary to cause behaviours, and the
simplistic notion of neurotransmitter changes driving behaviour has
no empirical support (Butt, 2004).
Despite all the appeals to
neurotransmitters, it has never been established in any studies that
they are the causal mechanism for our behaviour.
Certain behaviours
may be correlated with changes in neurotransmitters, however, this
alone is insufficient for any explanation of behaviour. For
instance, testosterone may be said to make us more aggressive and
research has shown that playing sports produces high levels of
testosterone. However, this does not necessarily mean aggressive
behaviour and violence will result, although we can observe there is
a correlation (cited in Butt, 2004).
This suggests that
dimensionality cannot be explained in terms of neurotransmitters
alone, and consequently we are unable to account for the complexities
of human behaviour by merely appealing to neurotransmitters pushing
us back and forth along a categorised dimension.
A New Approach to Traits
Assigning
traits and categorisations is a natural propensity to social beings
like us. These descriptions are useful in our day to day lives and
interpersonal relationships. However, once the light of reality is
allowed to illuminate the landscape, we find nothing tangible and no
solid basis for grounding traits. In this orthodox trait theory we
have found that there are no grounds to assert that neurotransmitters
are a necessary cause of behaviours.
We need not deny there is any
correlation or that they play a role, but it is certainly asking far
too much to suppose that neurotransmitters can fully account for the
dimensionality of our behaviour.
Furthermore, such an account has no
coherent justification for explaining how extremes of
uncharacteristic behaviour occur in traumatic circumstances. We can
go from the pits of despair to elation in an instant, and we can ask
for an account of how neurotransmitters can fluctuate so much so as
to cause this, particularly when we are trying to make sense of
behaviour in terms of traits?
Clearly, we are giving an impoverished
account by pointing merely to fixed traits. As we have seen there is
little basis for them, nor is there any evidence to suggest any
enduring mechanism is responsible for them.
So,
given that there clearly are patterns in peoples behaviour, does it
not make sense to try and categorise them?
Yes, it does make sense
and we use these terms when describing people, however, we are now
left with the question of where do these categorisations originate
from, if not from psychological and biological dispositions?
It is
one thing to deny the existence of these traits, yet we must be able
to convincingly account for why the notion of traits is so
widespread. So, where does this illusion come from?
Part VI here...
Part VI here...
Sunday, 21 September 2014
Traits
of Temperament & Character
At
this point it may be argued that persistence or 'relaible' is the
wrong sort of thing to constitute a fixed trait. We might divide the
trait realm in to traits of character and traits of temprament. This
is an argument favoured by Helen Fisher
in 'This Will Make You Smarter'
"Personality
is composed of two fundamentally different types of traits: those of
‘character;’ and those of ‘temperament.’ Your character
traits stem from your experiences. Your childhood games; your
family’s interests and values; how people in your community express
love and hate; what relatives and friends regard as courteous or
perilous; how those around you worship; what they sing; when they
laugh; how they make a living and relax: innumerable cultural forces
build your unique set of character traits. The balance of your
personality is your temperament, all the biologically based
tendencies that contribute to your consistent patterns of feeling,
thinking and behaving. As Spanish philosopher, Jose Ortega y Gasset,
put it, ‘I am, plus my circumstances.’ Temperament is the ‘I
am,’ the foundation of who you are". (Fisher, 2013)
Here
we see that Fisher divides the trait domain in to two components
which consist of temperament and character. She claims that
temperament is the foundation of who you are. Then, we also have
traits developed by experience, that is our character. In this sense,
she is trying to say there is some fixed essence to us, but also a
malleable component much like Eyesenck. Given that in our previous
example, my persistence was learned, we could pass this off as a
trait of experience, if we could really call it a trait at all. A
trait theorist may reject my persistence is a trait of temperament,
and try to run another argument in favour of traits which might run
like this.
John
is an introvert who clearly has a shy trait since he has a social
anxiety disorder of some kind. It is evident that we observe
consistent and regular withdrawal behaviours when he is surrounded by
strangers, and he has always been like this. This points to an
enduring mechanism that causes this behaviour, therefore, traits do
exist.
Constructing
an argument in this way, we have delineated between experience and
some fixed essence of an individual. That is to say, persistence is
the kind of thing derived from our experience, but there is some
particular immutable hard wired aspect to our personality which is
the biological foundation of what we refer to as ourselves.
However,
this might not be a tenable claim to make if we consider the
following. If we take John and put him in a different situation i.e.
with two friends he knows well, it might be reasonable to suggest
this shy trait would disappear. This means that the appearance of the
trait is contingent on a specific context, namely when confronted
with strangers. In this instance, it would appear that a specific
stimulus is required in order to trigger this disposition. Here, an
explanation might look like this.
Stimulus
– Perceptual recognition - Neurotransmitters released -
Behavioural response
This
may well be observable in a series of events and it is reasonable to
draw this conclusion, however, we need not hold to the claim this is
a fixed enduring disposition. It is recognised by psychologists that
cognitive behavioural therapy (CBT) can affect changes to people who
suffer with social anxiety disorder.
Essentially, if we take someone
like John we could put him through a series of therapy sessions and
over time he could well become cured of his social anxiety. On this
account it seems that these dispositions are not enduring at all, they are actually malleable and a product of his dysfunctional thinking. In this sense,
we can question the assumption that there are hard wired biological
aspects to our personality.
Proponents
of trait theory try to appeal to certain aspects of personality being
malleable, and others which are not. It is clear here that in order
to account for this, a trait theorist points to both an experiential
component, and a fixed biological component. However, by appealing to
these dual mechanisms, trait theorists are both having their cake and
eating it. How can we justifiably claim that on the one hand there
are experiential traits that are malleable and fixed biological
traits that are also malleable? In order to assert a solid foundation
for this “I am”, it would be necessary to put this shyness trait
in to a biological category. How could one possibly be shy and this
not be part of their temperament?
Right
here we run in to a clear contradiction in terms. This division in to
traits of temperament and character appears to be underspecified at
best and at worst incoherent. It is recognised that people can go
through major changes to their behaviour, especially when we consider
the transition from a child to an adult. It might be pertinent to
assign an aggressive temperament to a child, but how then do we
explain this transition to a calm and relaxed adult using the idea of
fixed traits? Clearly, the distinction between temperament and
character cannot be maintained since we need to appeal to
malleability of temperament, and it seems this division is clearly a
product of reification. That is, we have mistakenly granted this
conceptual division concrete existence, when it does not exist. It
would be incumbent on a trait theorist to specify this difference
coherently, and it appears that this difficulty is insurmountable.
The
other option available here is to bite the bullet and say there are
no fixed traits. That even our temperament is malleable, as we are
beings that change over time. In this sense, Trait theory could
incorporate John's cure and allow that this foundation of who we are
can shift over time.
However,
the difficulties for trait theory begin to become apparent once we
expose the assumptions needed for this idea to work...
Part V here...
Part V here...
Sunday, 7 September 2014
The
traits that we use in everyday conversation appear in the form of a
predicate in grammatical terms. That is, they form the part of the
clause that describes the subject. So for example, we could say “John
is shy” and the 'is shy' portion is our predicate. This is
how we tend to describe people in an objective capacity. However,
this does become problematic when we try and apply it across the
board.
A
trait that I liked to apply to myself was my strong level of
persistence. Since Eyesenck does not use the word persistent,
I find the closest matching trait from his chart which is reliable.
I do not get easily dissuaded and I have an unwavering ability to
push forward towards my goals even in difficult circumstances. This
is perhaps my strongest trait and something I considered to make me
who I am.
This description is rather inaccurate though because I was
not always so persistent. In fact, I used to be a quitter and found
it difficult to see things through when I was younger. I sometimes
used to look at things that had a degree of difficulty and did not
even bother entertaining giving it a go, quickly dismissing them as
too difficult. When I did try, I often ran out of momentum and my
interest waned quickly.
In
later life I developed an interest in many difficult things such as
producing music, writing philosophy, and martial arts. These are not
things you can just give a quick go and become a master at. These are
things that require a serious degree of commitment and also many
failures through trial and error. By applying myself to certain
endeavours, I found I got a great deal of satisfaction from them and
I was willing to persist at them for this reason.
When completing my
degree I did not find the same level of satisfaction in doing the
work, but I did focus on the end result, which I believed would give
me a great deal of satisfaction. Even though there were times when
studying drove me to despair, especially when I was sat in the house
whilst it was 30° outside during the summer, I managed to stick it
out right through till the end. In this sense, when we perceive that
it is something of value then persistence becomes something that
naturally flows from this.
When
we look at it in this sense it seems I actually learned to become
persistent rather than having it as a natural trait. However, if
someone in a job interview asked me “What is your strongest trait”?
I
would reply “My persistence”. It is plain then I have led myself
into self deceit and there is no enduring quality about me that is
persistent.
It
is just simply the fact that I persist at doing things that I deem to
be of value.
I
would not demand to continue a picnic when the weather turned
inclement, and clearly my persistence trait would disappear on such
an occasion. Personally, I find more value in sticking at difficult
tasks, and I do not find things that come with little effort very
rewarding. However, this does not mean it is some enduring quality
that I possess more so than anybody else.
We
are all willing to persist at something that we believe is of value
to us, and to say this is a personality trait, would be conflating it
with our preferences. Our preferences are real but we were trying to
point to enduring 'traits' in order to predict our behaviour. Our
preferences, as we know, change over time and sometimes quite
drastically too.
For instance, you probably didn't like the taste of
alcohol or olives when you were younger, and I seriously doubt that
you are interested in playing with action figures or Dolls any more.
Anyhow, I digress here and this is a subject worthy of future
exploration in its own right.
The
main point is this.
Do
you see how easy it is to concoct an identity story?
By
overcoming adversity at University and persisting with my endeavours
through all the difficult parts, I have constructed an enduring
quality about myself that is grounded in fiction. In the past I could
have used this as a device to delude myself about my triumph over
adversity, or to try and coerce or manipulate the way people might
think about me.
The
reality is sometimes I persist at things and other times I don't.
That
is about as far as any chain of reasoning can be established here,
and all we are left with is a miserable tautology, when we expected
to find some enduring quality of my 'personality'. The thing that
determines whether or not I do persist is simply whether I deem it to
be of value. Very simply, we are looking to contingencies of
circumstance that determine whether or not we perform particular
behaviours.
That
is, the context we find ourselves in is the factor which determines
our behaviour.
To
point to some enduring quality that 'makes me the person who I am'
clearly seems to point to the mistakes we made in the first part of
this essay. This is where we referred to 'categorisation' as being an
incoherent means of assigning traits to people, since there is a
dimensional quality to their behaviours. Furthermore, we can invent
new categories to rationalise our stories, and the above is an
instance where I have conjured up a personality trait out of thin
air.
It
seems that we all find it too easy to make the error of rigidly
categorising ourselves and to compound this problem, some of our
categorisations may not be positive traits like persistence. Have you
ever categorised yourself as a loser, unlovable, clumsy?
Well
guess what.
You
are using the very same mechanism of delusion to conceptualise
yourself. When we take a look at the imposing fortress of such
categorisations, we need only revise our view point, and realise it
was folly all along.
This
argument might not hold with some folk though, and we might say this
is the wrong sort of thing to call a trait, and challenge this
argument by splitting traits in to two types....
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)
Popular Posts
-
It seems difficult to capture exactly what we mean by looking so I am writing this out in the hope that we can clear up the issue a littl...
-
Having looked at our concept of identity and reduced it down to two types, we are able to look at how there are certain presumptions made w...
-
I did not want to spend too much time covering old ground but felt it necessary to put the past firmly behind me. I want to discuss t...
-
Of course we were not around in those days when we are asked to lay something on the line to defend our freedoms. It was a long time since ...
-
Where to begin - Part I here Dishonesty - An Introduction This word has a negative connotation straight off the bat. It does suggest tha...
-
As the January blues begin to wear away, well, I am only saying that for dramatic effect. The truth is the blues that I am supposed to have...
-
Where to begin - Part I here An introduction to dishonesty - here What is the self? 3. Changing the story to fit the contradictory fact...
-
Firstly, a happy new year all! Been a while since I had time to post, so as the new year highs fade, it is time that I get motivated while ...
-
The sound of the ruthless truth battle cry. Worthless post, nothing of value to glean from here apart from laughing at how fanatical I was. ...
-
Where to begin - Part I here An introduction to dishonesty - here Here are some excerpts from a thread on Truth Strike which illustrates ...