- Butt, T. (2012) 'Critical Readings in Social Psychology', Ch. 3, 2nd edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
- Butt, T. (2004) 'Understanding People', ch.1, Basingstoke & New York, Palgrave Macmillan.
- Eysenck, H.J & Rachman, S. (2012 [1965]) 'Dimensions of Personality', in Butt, T (2012) 'Critical Readings in Social Psychology', ch.3, 2nd edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
- Fisher, H (2013) Extract of essay taken from 'On Temperament' in Brockman, J (2013 [2012]) This will make you smarter.Last Accessed 23/11/14
- Holloway, W. (2012) 'Social Psychology Matters', ch.3, 2nd edition, Milton Keynes, The Open University.
- Richards, G. (2002) 'Putting Psychology in its Place:A Critical Historical Overview', ch. 18, 2nd edition, Sussex, Psychology Press.
Sunday, 23 November 2014
The Myth of the Enduring Personality - Part VIII (conclusion)
Conclusion
Having
outlined the notion of personality traits here, it seems that many
new questions are raised. One of the first ones that may appear is
why I've gone to the trouble of highlighting Eyesenck's flawed
personality trait studies.
Surely I could be accused of constructing
a strawman argument from 1960s research and launching an attack
against that? Furthermore, you may be wondering why I have written
such a lengthy mini series and how this is relevant. Well, I will
spell out why I went to the trouble of doing this semi-academic
piece, and highlight what it might achieve.
It is of
little surprise that Eyesenck's ideas have caught on. The basic
ideas behind his argument have formed the basis for much on going
research. It is only within the last 10 years that the voices of
critics like Mischel have been heeded in the mainstream.
Meanwhile, the mainstream has had to try and fight off the eliminative
materialist claims that we should be abandoning the folk theory and
trying to form a proper theory of mind over the past 30 years.
It
seems we are at the stage where we have to pay attention to the way
in which we have carved up the psychological domain. This means
we're going to have to re-evaluate the categorisations that we have
traditionally imposed.
The endurance of Eyesenck's theory bears
testament to the fact that he appeals to common sense and appeals to
the way in which we have been carving up the psychological domain.
The main
problem with trait theory centres around the assumption that traits
actually exist. There are newer, and presumably better, personality
theories around these days but they all make
the assumption that we fit in to categories or types.
As I have
stated in this discussion, we do conform to predictable patterns of
behaviour at times and we certainly do not need to deny this. Nor do
we need to deny that categories have practical use. We have also
admitted that we have a cultural assumption that traits exist built
right in to our language.
It is the tendency of the human mind to
divide the world in to categories and using traits is one way in
which people in our social worlds become intelligible.
Implicit
in this view is that these traits are independent from our agency.
That is, we have no control over our tendency to get angry, be
pessimistic etc. In this sense we are referring to some kind of
mechanism that we have no control over. Interestingly enough, we
identify strongly with our personality traits and we believe them to
make some kind of statement about who we really are.
We might be
tempted to identify other aspects of our body which we have no
control over, like being ginger or being optimistic. We may identify
with things that we consciously choose, like being a raver or
whatever it is the kids call themselves these days (Yes, I'm not down
with the kids anymore!). However, it is usually just the case that we
utilise circular logic to form a web of deceit, which masquerades as
our identity, that prevents us from entertaining the truth about the
illusory self.
The
notion of self hood is reliant in part on the multiple “I am 'a', I
am also 'b', and 'c'” modes of identification. E.g. I am ginger, I
am optimistic, I am a raver. It is likely that during your
phenomenological investigation in to the self you will try to say
that the self is identical to x, y, or z.
E.g. The self is the brain,
the self is the body, The self is memory and so on.
Nobody
ever takes the time to look behind what these concepts refer to in
real life, as these modes are representative of the constraints in
which we think.
This
is why it is not a logical endeavour to realise Anatta.
The
trick to getting this Anatta insight is in part exposing the
emptiness of those a, b, c labels, and then refuting the assumptions
that the self is x, y, or z.
Once these notions have been smashed to
pieces, then it is a simple case of honest looking. I am going to
post the above paragraph in numerous places because it is a succinct
outline of the basic process you need to use.
I used to harp on about
looking, but it is also necessary to smash apart the web of deceit by
utilising a bit of logic first. When you see these assumptions no
longer work logically you can discard them and systematically
demolish the foundations upon which the illusory self is based.
We
all start out from a position where we are bounded by the belief that
we are an enduring self that has such and such 'properties'. We have
a tendency to objectify ourselves as having the 'properties' of
traits, much like we can treat other people as objects of experience.
I wanted to draw this parallel here, not because we normally treat
friends and family like objects, but because we think in terms of all
'things' as having enduring properties.
What
we mean here is the way we describe subjects and objects in dualistic
terms, results in us assigning attributes to people which are of
course consistent with our categorisation of traits.
These
traits are predicated as aspects of the self, much like properties
are the predicates of objects in our language.
So
take the 'outgoing' trait as an example. Imagine that you are
outgoing and sociable and by some awful freak event, you lose the use
of your vocal cords and become dumb. What would happen to this
personality trait then? You might claim 'I'm outgoing and sociable'
previously.
However, what would we make of this claim if you were
struck down with this awful tragedy?
Nothing
would have changed about your so called traits, however, this
outgoing trait is contingent on your being able to talk. In this
sense, the predicate would become unintelligible to somebody who just
met you, and did not know you prior to your unfortunate change in
circumstance.
Clearly, these constructs are quite empty when we
consider such extremes.
When
we are talking about contingencies of circumstance these are rather
fleeting things which can easily change, instead of being the solid
and enduring things we think they are. We
can start to look at our own personality traits and look at the ways
in which we think they define us.
The point of this whole piece
really, is to smash apart the solidity of personality traits and
highlight the shaky grounds on which they are based.
It is not so
much that we needed to disprove traits exist (although I have cast
serious doubt on the claim), it is just to show that the solid
assumptions we use to prop up our notions of selfhood are really
quite flimsy when we examine them with a degree of scrutiny.
Once
we start to hack away at the logic behind personality traits, it
seems more and more likely that we are really dealing with an
arbitrary notion of category construction, that is purely linguistic.
It
should be noted at this point, that different cultures have different
categories of behaviour. As such, cross-cultural trait models have a
cut down five trait model, to try and apply it universally across the
board. In this sense it is only our arrogance that leads us to assume
that there are a definitive of set of objective trait correlates,
that conform to the English language.
The
reality seems to suggest that traits are merely the construction of
personal values using shared language. In more scientific terms,
traits theory is an attempt to treat people as having objective
aspects, that can be medically categorised and diagnosed.
This
of course has its roots in the orthodoxy of physicalism, which is
now an untenable position in philosophy of mind and has since been
superseded with functionalism. I argued earlier that we cannot
delineate between traits and our personal construction of meaning
convincingly.
For this reason, I am convinced that a revised
functionalist account of trait theory could not work, but
functionalism certainly may be able to account for behaviour by
identifying patterning in neural networks. However, this would
constitute an as yet unspecified theory, and would abandon the
constraints of traditional notions of traits.
This new theory would
be something that perhaps many eliminative materialists would
endorse.
The
evidence for the personal construction theory of traits seems to fit
our observations. The lack of evidence for traditional notions of
traits is compounded by the problems we have when we point to
conventions of language.
Could
it really be the case that nobody has objective personality traits,
and the myth of the enduring personality is a fiction? For me, the
fact that our ideas about personality are completely empty could be
somewhat disconcerting and radical on the one hand.
It seems that
when I think about the ones I love and that they have no personality,
other than what I construct in my own mind is counter intuitive.
However, once we factor in the multiplicity of events and the
vicissitudes of our different behaviours, it becomes clear that these
categorisations of traits are too rigid for the rich and wonderful
varieties of behaviour that our fellow human beings are capable of.
When
viewed in this sense, it seems that quite the opposite is the case
and traits are counter-intuitive.
The
notion of trying to apply a narrow series of categories that apply to
traits, would be far too restrictive to account for the dynamic
nature of the unfolding of our lives. If we were only capable of
behaving along a dimensional axis for each trait, then we would be
somewhat robotic and more predictable in our responses to life's
events.
The fact of the matter is that we are far more unpredictable
and are capable of surprising acts, and confounding expectations. We
try to impose order on the world by using traits but this does not
entail that the way we do so, or the way we learned culturally to do
so, is definitive in any way.
If
we take the view of Heidegger, the subject/ object dichotomy is
merely one way of being, and is a useful way to look at the world.
However, restricting ourselves to this view means that we miss out on
the modes of being where we don't view people as having properties.
Such times would be when we are in the throes of sporting
competition, having a laugh with friends in the pub, or losing
yourself in a lovers kiss.
The
point here, is simply that we need to differentiate between the way
we think about people objectively when we reflect on them, and the
way we experience them in the flow of life. It makes sense that we
try to make predictions about how others might behave, or rationalise
and criticise peoples actions.
When doing this though, we are always
doing it in a temporal sense outside of the present moment. When
using traits we are talking about past and future actions.
I
will leave it for you to decide where trait theory fits in to the
present moment, but rest assured you will find it difficult to find
relevance in the present moment, other than within a temporal
narrative about time. That is, every time we think about traits it is
in a temporal sense and does not conform to our 'being in the world'
direct experience of socialising.
We could of course be talking about
drama when socialising in the present moment, and we could be
focussed on why someone acted in such and such a manner. Again
though, we would be referring to our temporal ideas and our
experience of traits in the present moment would be limited to the
act of talking itself, and the mental phenomena that arises during
our chain of reasoning.
It
seems then, that the notion of an enduring personality is nothing
more than a myth in the grand scheme of things. Particularly where we
use the categorisations available in our linguistic community.
It
was an unfounded assumption that these categorisations actually
related to physical states and whilst it appears logical to divide
the domain of traits in this way, we've seen that this is actually
empty.
It seems that personality is a mysterious phenomenon that we
think we can know, but we cannot easily, or coherently, conceptualise
it in the way we thought we could.
References:
Monday, 17 November 2014
The Myth of the Enduring Personality - Part VII
F.A.E - The Fundamental Attribution Error
In
rating people we have a propensity to commit the 'fundamental
attribution error'
which is where we
overvalue
the effect of human agency, and underestimate the effect of the
present situation in explaining behaviour (Butt, 2004).
To illustrate, when we have to slam on the breaks because of
someone's driving, we may well blame the poor skill and idiotic
driving of another.
However, we might be overlooking the fact that
they are lost and are unsure of where they are going, and had a
moment of panic. In this sense, we are biased towards prioritising
human agency, and underestimate the degree to which a situation
determines behaviour.
If
we apply this to Eysenck, he assumed widespread use of words by the general population pointed to the underlying objectivity of traits. Whilst we
need not deny there are stable patterns in peoples behaviour,
Eysenck's research was situated within this folk psychology paradigm
and any results he derived were simply reinforcing his theories about
the existence of traits, without an attempt to test the validity of
them.
In this sense, his entire research project begged the question,
since he simply assumed that our categorisations pointed to real
enduring qualities. In any case, any results he derived were simply a
collection of people committing the fundamental attribution error,
and this undermines his claim to objective validity.
The fundamental attribution error demonstrates our propensity to conform to the general populations assumptions about traits in everyday discourse, and assume these shape our agency. However, what we find is that Eyesenck simply reinforced these assumptions, by getting people to take part in his research program and not, even undertaking an independent verification of the existence of such traits. Moreover, his statistical measurement technology was flawed and we see that the case for objectivity here is very flimsy.
Check out Dustinland's wicked cartoons: http://dustinland.com/archives/archives626.html |
This problem arises because Eyesenck simply drew a pattern from
statistical inference of observations as justification for his
theory. As Richards (2002) points out, the very psychometric survey
measurements that we undertake can cause reification; where we
falsely grant objective reality to the thing being measured.
To
give an example, we could design a religious survey in 1700 say, that
tried to measure devoutness to Christianity. We could make statements
such as "Homosexuality is a sin and punishable by death",
or "Witchcraft is rife in this village".
We could collate a
number of psychometric surveys and provide statistically derived
empirical results. However, from these results all we have achieved
is measuring a bunch of worthless religious assumptions.
We have not
proved that these assumptions are true, we have merely taken for
granted their truth and produced a load of mathematical workings out
to support our folly.
Furthermore, these questions may have seemed
valid in 1700 but were we to try and ask them now, they would sound
quite ridiculous to any Christian. In this case, if we have
supposedly measured devoutness to religion and the statements are
irrelevant now, we can ask what exactly would we have measured back
then?
The simple answer is that we have reified the concept
devoutness to religion and
would have been engaged in sophistry.
What
this tells us is that any psychometric studies are based on
assumptions, and they produce a load of clever sounding mathematics
that purport to back up these assumptions. All this is done without
ever actually backing up these assumptions with evidence.
What we
really find is that this methodology is utterly worthless as a
measure of truth, and in fact, this has been utilised as a tool by
those of lowly scruples, to engage in the most wretched acts of deceit.
It
should be of little surprise that this is the tool of choice for
charlatans in marketing, studies of 'public opinion', and your impotent government.
This
dangerous tool has been used to subvert the need to make claims based
on evidence, and you should be suspicious of any statistical
manipulations that are thrown at you.
However, we can
forgive Eyesenck as these facts were not known at the time, and he
genuinely believed he was advancing science. It should be clear to
you now though, that this questionnaire style methodology is fundamentally flawed and is
still abused to this day by those who engage in the art of
statistical manipulation.
Mischel's Criticisms
To
cast further doubt on Eyesenck's research, Mischel (1968) started to
assess the evidence for trait theories and found the key assumption
that Eysenck had made was incorrect. It should be starting to become
clear that Eyesenck had simply assumed stable personalities were
based on a structural arrangement of traits.
What Mischel discovered
was that this assumption is not justified. Mischel cited extensive
evidence that suggested the attributing of traits reflected the
prejudice of the person doing the attributing, who had to draw on a
culturally shared trait theory to frame their observations. Given
that we use trait theory in everyday parlance, any observation is
necessarily going to be couched in terms of traits. However, this
does not necessarily mean our cultural categorisations are pointing
to anything concrete.
Mischel
cited a study that used Eyesenck's methodology of rating people from
behind a screen, and using a psychometric survey to measure the
responses. However, this time they observed strangers briefly in one
condition, and in another observed people whom they knew personally.
This study yielded a striking finding that went right to the heart of
this kind of objective methodology. It was found that those doing the
rating,
produced the same stable trait structure in strangers that they
observed very briefly, as in those that they knew well
(Butt, 2012).
This showed that under controlled conditions, subjects
were prejudicial in their attribution of personality
traits to strangers, and were willing to attribute them on very
little evidence. It also showed that these attributions were based on
the way they personally attributed traits to those they knew well
(Butt, 2004).
This
clearly demonstrated the error on which personality research was
based. It
is only natural, given the knowledge was situated in a paradigm that
accepted folk psychological doctrine, that through seeing statistical
patterns, practitioners could devise psychological categories for
people in order to determine treatments.
This kind of categorisation
is now widely acknowledged to be unreliable and PCT actually denies
this is useful, since it aims to understand the individual and
acknowledges there are many individual differences, rather than
narrow categorical dimensions.
Interestingly,
PCT would embrace this subjective aspect of a person doing the
personality construction, because when listening to how they
construct someone's personality we can uncover some of the meanings
this process has for them, and how they perceive the world.
To this
extent as a phenomenological exercise we can discover how people form
their constructions, and perhaps some of the assumptions participants make. However, this endeavour fits in to the field of social psychology, and we would be moving beyond the scope of this essay.
Conclusion here
Conclusion here
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)
Popular Posts
-
I did not want to spend too much time covering old ground but felt it necessary to put the past firmly behind me. I want to discuss t...
-
It seems difficult to capture exactly what we mean by looking so I am writing this out in the hope that we can clear up the issue a littl...
-
This post started out as a short piece about belief but I let it roll and now its going to be a series examining belief, the resultant cogn...
-
Having looked at our concept of identity and reduced it down to two types, we are able to look at how there are certain presumptions made w...
-
Where to begin - Part I here An introduction to dishonesty - here Here are some excerpts from a thread on Truth Strike which illustrates ...
-
A few pertinent insights here, and clearly explained. The cause and effect thing is worth scrolling down for, and the ideas about time are, ...
-
Where to begin - Part I here Dishonesty - An Introduction This word has a negative connotation straight off the bat. It does suggest tha...
-
Of course we were not around in those days when we are asked to lay something on the line to defend our freedoms. It was a long time since ...
-
I will have to rewrite this post eventually as the ideas are under developed. The piece is pertaining to the philosophical problem of othe...
-
Hi all, long delay since the new year as have been busy with renovating my new house. Yes, even without a self we need mortgages and somewh...