Part 1 of 8
Are
we different from each other? This might seem a very obvious question
to ask on the face of it. Immediately we can think of various ways in
which we do differ. For instance, we might point to obvious physical
facts such as hair colour. We would then point to genetic differences
as being the cause of these differences.
This is only superficial
though, and one of the more fundamental things that we want to
explain is how are we individually different from each other in
psychological terms? One question we might want to explain as
psychologists is this.
Why
do we behave differently from each other?
It
is at this point that we like to invoke the concept of personality
traits. Attributing personality traits to describe the enduring ways
in which individuals differ is everyday common practice. We have all
done this in the past and a common example might look something like
this.
I may describe someone as 'shy' and upon meeting them you might
notice they seem guarded. You would infer the cause for their
behaviour is because of the 'shy trait' I described, which determines
their behaviour.
The
main reasons for thinking that individuals have traits are that if we
take two people and apply the same stimulus, we may see different
behavioural outcomes.
We may infer that there is a fixed trait that
determines this behaviour, and in future instances we can predict
relatively accurately how this person may behave in similar
circumstances.
So
having outlined this basic assumption that we have fixed 'traits'
that determine our behaviour, it is now my aim to attack this
conception, and demonstrate that personality traits are actually a
fiction. They are an artefact of an outdated 'folk psychology'
conception of mind.
By folk psychology, we mean the general taken for
granted concepts we use to explain how the mind operates. For
example, to explain someone's thought processes, I might use concepts
to say they 'believe', they have 'attitude' X, they are 'emotional',
they have trait Y and so forth.
What
we have discovered is that these concepts are underspecified and
incoherent in explaining the workings of the mind on a scientific
basis.
That
is, using these categorisations of mental states does not conform to
how the mind works. It might be plausible for us to say that someone
needs to change their attitude, and this common sense description
captures what we mean. However, when we try to find the mental state
that conforms to the concept 'attitude', we draw a blank.
Essentially our problem boils down to the way in which we divide the
psychological domain in to language. Given that over 2000 years ago
these concepts were formed for explanatory purposes, there is no
reason to suppose that these concepts have any relation to any state
that occurs in the brain. For this reason, we refer to these concepts
as folk psychology, much like we refer to historical stories as
'folklore'.
This
position where we reject folk psychologies categorisations is known
as eliminative materialism (See Churchland 1979). Eliminative
materialism denies that these common folk categories of mental states
actually exist in real life. The idea that we possess enduring
'behavioural traits' has been called in to question by numerous
researchers. Trying to explain the mind in terms of this primitive
concept has been unsuccessful thus far.
The problem is that this
framework, which has guided much of our research, used to assume that
these traits were fixed dispositions that had causal relationships
with our behaviour. I will try to show there is no conceivable way in
which these traits can be separated out in to these simple
categories. Whilst our linguistic construction of folk concepts and
common sense notions are useful in communication, they have had
little success in the sciences.
Eliminative materialism supposes that
we reject the folk conception of the mind in favour of a proper
scientific theory of mind. This newer fine grained theory will usurp
our categories and make folk psychologies primitive notions of
traits, attitudes, beliefs, etc, redundant.
Whilst
this investigation is not an endorsement of eliminative materialism
per se, I share the view that we should completely reject the way
that folk psychology has carved up the mental domain.
It
is certainly a useful heuristic for everyday communication, however,
it ultimately has no relevance to any kind of explanatory framework
that will yield anything fruitful in the sciences. Others have
rejected the account of individual differences explained by traits,
and I am not the first to explore this area by any means.
I propose
to explain the theoretical underpinnings of trait theory and then
refute it on the grounds that it is incoherent. I will show the
traits that we actually think exist, are actually in the eye of the
beholder. That is, we make judgements about people that rarely have
any kind of objective grounding, and we fool ourselves in to
believing that we are identifying traits in others.
What
might cause these different traits we claim to observe?
To
start with, we might want to look at what might give us this idea. At
this level of explanation we are accustomed to look towards the
neurological wiring of the brain as providing us with a suitable
explanation. We are all familiar with the
concept of nature and nurture, which is where we are looking to
discover whether genetic factors or someone's early conditioning is
what determines their behaviour.
A
'shy trait' then, means that we are describing some kind of enduring
biological or psychological mechanism, or perhaps a combination of
the two, which determines behaviour and causes people to act in
predictable ways.
This
would be a useful description for us to use because, as human beings,
we have a tendency and need to predict peoples behaviour.
As
a general rule we like to assign a variety of traits to people. When
we are asked to describe a person, lets say a friend, how would you
do this? Most often we would reel off a shopping list of traits like
kind, generous, and so forth. These are the type of words we would
use to give an objective description of people we know, however, we
run into a problem rather quickly.
0 comments:
Post a Comment